Monday, July 16, 2007

International Criminal Court

This is the html version of the file http://www.idsa.in/publications/strategic-analysis/2003/jan/atul.pdf.G o o g l e automatically generates html versions of documents as we crawl the web.To link to or bookmark this page, use the following url: http://www.google.com/search?q=cache:dN9AJHx2z5wJ:www.idsa.in/publications/strategic-analysis/2003/jan/atul.pdf+atul+bharadwaj&hl=en&ct=clnk&cd=2&gl=in
Google is neither affiliated with the authors of this page nor responsible for its content.
These search terms have been highlighted:
atul
bharadwaj
Page 1
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
1
International Criminal Court and the
Question of Sovereignty
Atul Bharadwaj
Abstract
Appalled by the increasing brutality and emboldened by the
collapse of ideological barriers, international law now intends to
cross the rubicon and reach out for criminals hiding behind the
veil of sovereignty. It aims to sensitize the world against gross
human rights violations through the threat of legal action. The
rapid entry of the Rome Statute on July 1, 2002 heralds a new
era in international politics. It opens new avenues for the
international community to monitor human rights violations
within states and bring the delinquent individuals to trial.
One of the main reasons for the court to come into existence
after the end of the Cold War is that many crimes committed
against humanity have been ignored by states either due to
'military necessity' or under the national sovereignty and
territorial integrity clause. The ICC does involve a certain
sacrifice of sovereignty because it envisages asserting itself
when a state refuses or fails to use its national criminal justice
apparatus to deal with the perpetrator of crimes against
humanity.
This paper argues that the ICC challenges the exclusivity of
sovereign states. ICC imposes certain restrictions and limits on
state authority and competes with the state in the exercise of
authority.
-*-
Announcing the entry into force of the International Criminal Court (ICC),
the UN Secretary-General Kofi Annan, said, "is a great victory for justice and
for world order-a turn away from the rule of brute force, and towards the rule
of law." He further added, "The process we are now witnessing marks a
decisive break with the cynical worldview", according to which in Stalin's
words, "a single death is a tragedy, a million deaths is a statistic".
1
During the Cold War, violations of humanitarian law were generally
brushed under the carpet due to political expediency. International law till the
end of the Cold War had overcome many temptations to breach the territorial
boundaries of the nation-state to discipline erring individuals. The principle of
'non-interference in the internal affairs' had often prevented the international
Page 2
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
2
community from taking any action. Moreover, international society had lacked
the coercive or deterrence power to prevent or punish the violations of human
rights by individuals.
Appalled by the ever-increasing brutality and emboldened by the collapse
of ideological barriers, the international community now intends to cross the
rubicon and reach out for criminals hiding behind the veil of sovereignty. It
aims to sensitize the world against gross human rights violations through the
threat of legal action. The rapid entry into force of the Rome Statute on July 1,
2002 heralds a new era in international politics. It opens new avenues for the
international community to monitor human rights violations within states and
bring the delinquent individuals to trial.
This paper argues that the ICC challenges the exclusivity of sovereign
states. The ICC imposes certain restrictions and limits on state authority and
competes with the state in the exercise of authority. However, the onus of
protecting and in fact, enhancing their sovereign status now rests more with
states than ever before. By upholding the principles of international law within
their territories, states can now prevent supranational interventions. This could
lead states to value justice over narrow political considerations. James Gow
has identified this shift in the state's primary source of sovereignty from the
'will of the people' to its obligations towards maintaining an international
equilibrium as 'the revolution in the sovereignty principle.
2
The paper is divided into two parts. The first part briefly touches upon the
formation of the ICC and its basic structure. Part two deals with the impact of
the ICC on sovereignty. Firstly, it looks at the metamorphosis of the individual
from 'object' to 'subject' in the eyes of international law. Secondly, it examines
the impact of ICC on the changing nature of the sovereignty discourse.
Background to ICC
In July 1998, the Diplomatic Conference of Plenipotentiaries on the
Establishment of an ICC concluded by adopting a statute for such a court.
3
The statute's principal inspiration came from the Nuremberg and Tokyo
Page 3
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
3
Tribunals.
4
The process of the Rome Statute was further guided by the
experience acquired from the operation of two ad-hoc International Criminal
Tribunals (ICTY and ICTR) set up to deal with prosecution of individuals for
violations of international criminal law in Yugoslavia and Rwanda.
5
The seeds for an international criminal court were sown in the year 1864
by Gustave Monynier, one the founders of the International Commission for
Red Cross (ICRC).
6
In 1947, Henri Donnedieli De Vabres, the French judge
on the International Military Tribunal at Nuremberg made a proposal for a
permanent court. The job of preparation for establishing an international
criminal court had begun in 1947. The UN General Assembly (UNGA)
entrusted the International Law Commission (ILC) with the task of drafting the
statute of an international criminal court derived from Article VI of the
Genocide Convention, along with the 'Nuremberg principles' and the 'Code of
Crimes against the Peace and Security of Mankind'. In addition, the UNGA
also constituted in 1952 a committee comprising representatives of 17 states,
for drafting the Statute of the ICC. In 1954, the ILC submitted its proposal for
the ICC. However, all further work on the ICC was suspended in the wake of
Cold War imperatives.
7
In 1989, Trinidad and Tobago initiated the process of establishing an
international court to try individuals charged in connection with criminal
offences, illicit trafficking in narcotic drugs across national frontiers and other
transnational activities.
8
In 1993, the UNGA again requested the International
Law Commission to prepare a draft statute for an ICC. The year 1994 saw the
UN General Assembly constituting an ad-hoc committee to review the draft.
The ad-hoc committee was followed by a preparatory committee, which met
thrice from 1996 to 1998 to clear issues pertaining to the text of the statute.
The ad-hoc committee was headed by Adriaan Bos, legal adviser to the
Ministry of Foreign Affairs of the Netherlands, who was replaced just prior to
the Rome conference by Philippe Kirsch, the legal adviser of the Ministry of
Foreign Affairs of Canada.
9
The final product of the preparatory committee,
which emerged in July 1998, had about 1400 brackets or points of
disagreements on various issues contained in the text.
10
Page 4
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
4
The entire process of negotiating the disagreements over the various
provisions of the statute was conducted in an organised manner. The 13 parts
of the statute were divided among various working groups for detailed
discussions. The working groups were provided adequate support through
informal consultations and discussions conducted among various political and
regional groups such as the Non-Aligned Movement, the European Union, the
Arab Group, the Latin America Group and many NGOs. The three major
groups of states which were formed during the conference were the 'like-
minded group' (LMG), the P-5 Group and the NAM Group. The LMG Group
consisted of 55 states, including many from Western Europe and Latin
America. The LMG group was the strongest supporter of the ICC and was
opposed to the moves of powerful nations to curtail the powers of the ICC.
The LMG's strength was augmented when Britain broke ranks with the P-5
and joined it just prior to the commencement of the conference. The change in
UK's stance had come about after the Labour Party victory in elections.
11
The
focus of the P-5 Group during the negotiations rested primarily on a strong
role for the Security Council vis-à-vis the court and the exclusion of use of
nuclear weapons from the list of weapons considered illegal in the statute.
The NAM Group comprised mainly India, Egypt and Mexico and argued
against the chief concerns of the P-5 nations. The NAM Group also advocated
a much less powerful ICC, which differed from the LMG position of a strong
ICC.
Role of the State in ICC
The ICC is a permanent body, which has come into existence through a
treaty among the member-states of the UN. It is binding only on the
signatories of the treaty. The ICC has no jurisdiction over states or legal
entities. Its purpose is to try individuals who are accused of committing crimes
of international concern. Such crimes include:

Genocide

Crime against humanity

War crimes and aggression
12
Page 5
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
5
The Rome Statute contains 13 parts, including 128 Articles. According to
Mahnoush Arsanjani, the three principles around which the Rome Statute was
built are:

Complimentarity-upholding the primacy of national courts over ICC.

Confining itself to dealing with more serious crimes against
international community as a whole.

Remaining within the realm of customary international law. That is, any
provision in the Statute, which conflicts with or is inconsistent with
general international law, shall be subordinate to it except in case of
Article 53 of the Vienna Convention on the Laws of Treaties, 1969.
The most debated and controversial part of the Statute is Part 2, which
deals with the Jurisdiction, Admissibility and Applicable Law. Articles 12-19
deal with the issues of jurisdiction of the court, the trigger mechanism and
admissibility.
Member-states of the UN have acted as the primary agent for creating an
international body like the ICC. Through the principle of complimentarity, the
ICC primarily displays its trust and respect for the national judicial system.
The court intends to deal only with the most serious crimes of concern to
international community as a whole and leaving the so-called conventional
crimes like terrorism and illicit drug trafficking to individual states'
jurisdiction.
13
It is argued that terrorism has not been included in the Statute
because of the absence of an internationally acceptable definition of terrorism.
Moreover, the perception of many countries with regard to terrorism is that it is
an individually driven project which is carried out by private individuals in an
isolated and not widespread or systematic manner. Therefore, to proceed
ahead with the formation of the ICC, controversial topics like terrorism,
supported by India, were conveniently dropped.
The Court intends to deal only with those cases where the national
procedures are unavailable or ineffective. In a statement before prepcom, on
December 8, 1997, Louise Arbour, Prosecutor of ICTY said, "Recourse to an
Page 6
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
6
international criminal forum will occur when horrendous crimes have been
committed with the collusion or impotence of national authorities."
14
One of the significant developments that could make states even more
vigilant against serious violations of international crimes is the inclusion in the
ICC Statute, of crimes perpetrated in civil wars, internal conflicts and non-
international armed conflicts. The Statute also omits any nexus between
crimes against humanity and armed conflict, thereby meaning that the crimes
against humanity can be committed in times of peace as well.
15
Only three powers are authorized to initiate the ICC 'trigger mechanism'.
That is, the case can be referred to the ICC only by the UN Security Council,
a party state or by the prosecutor acting on his or her own motion (proprio
motou). A non-party state can also refer the case to the ICC. But, in case of a
non-party state, Article 12 (3) of the Statute uses the term "the crime in
question" instead of "a situation in which one or more crimes within the
jurisdiction of the court appear to have been committed."
16
The prosecutor will
have the power to reject the referrals made by the UN Security Council and
the party states. During the negotiations the US had opposed the proprio
motou powers of the prosecutor, which the LMG Group had promoted. Finally,
the US was able to restrict the powers of the prosecutor by making him seek
the advice of the pre-trial chamber prior to proceeding with a proprio motou
investigation.
17
Granting the UN Security Council the right to trigger the ICC primarily
reinforces the argument that in the international order the concept of
sovereignty has various gradations depending on the power and position of
the state. The role of the Security Council in the ICC has been India's main
objection. According to Dilip Lahiri, the head of the Indian delegation at the
Rome Statute, "any pre-eminent role for the Security Council in triggering ICC
jurisdiction constitutes a violation of sovereign equality, as well as equality
before law, because it contains an assumption that the five veto-wielding
states do not commit the crimes covered by the ICC Statute."
18
The counter-
argument to India's position in Flavia Lattanzi's opinion is that the presence of
Page 7
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
7
the complimentarity principle will act as an umbrella which will cover the
powers of the Security Council under Chapter 7 in the initial phases at least.
19
According to M. Cherif Bassiouni, "ICC is based on the principle of
territorial criminal jurisdiction, and not on a theory of universality of criminal
jurisdiction", because only 'referrals' by the Security Council are de-linked
from "territoriality of any state, whether they are state parties or non-state
parties."
20
This means that the other two trigger mechanisms are related to
territorial criminal jurisdiction. However, in case of proprio motou, India's
objection is that, "the distinction between the sovereign authority of the states
on the one hand and the professional role of a prosecutor on the other should
be maintained", because, the matters pertaining to states cannot be handed
over to an individual prosecutor to initiate investigations suo motto and thus
trigger the jurisdiction of the Court.
21
The United States too has been
opposing the powers vested in the prosecutor, because it fears that the
discretionary powers placed in the hands of a prosecutor are antithetical to its
national sovereignty.
22
The US sees the ICC as an infringement of its
sovereign rights as a Superpower to carry out humanitarian and international
peace missions across the globe. The ICC will have the power to prosecute
US citizens and soldiers, who are spread across the globe in pursuit of
protecting US business and security interests.
23
In order to prevent such an
eventuality, Washington tried its best to differentiate between internal conflicts
and international armed conflicts. Initially, the US rejected the notion of
automatic jurisdiction for crime except genocide and proposed an opt-out
mechanism for war crimes and crimes against humanity. This proposal was
meant to protect US citizens who are the most involved globally and whose
actions could fall under the purview of war crimes and crimes against
humanity. The US did not show much concern for genocide because it knows
that such a crime is most likely to be applicable in case of internal conflicts
between the majority and minority community in smaller states.
24
The US also
tried in vain to put restrictions on the jurisdictional regime by proposing that
the consent of the territorial state and the state of nationality of the perpetrator
must be sought before trying the individual of a non-party state. For example,
under Article 12 (2), if the US (non-party state) armed forces commander
Page 8
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
8
attacks a marriage party in Afghanistan (party state) killing 100 children and
women, being a non-party state, the US has immunity from the court. But if
Afghanistan complains to ICC against the US commander for systematic
attack on its citizens, then the US commander is liable to be tried. He would
also not be able to seek immunity on the grounds that he was acting in an
official capacity. It is mainly this threat that small states may combine against
the US and browbeat it into accepting the diktats of the UN that is difficult for
the Bush administration to swallow.
In accordance with the provisions of the Statute, state parties are obliged
to "cooperate fully with the Court in its investigation and prosecution of crimes
within the jurisdiction of the Court."
25
While the Article, which deals with the
surrender of persons to the Court, uses the term 'request' for seeking the
cooperation of state parties in arrest and surrender of the concerned person,
party states are under international obligation to comply with the request.
Party states are duty bound to "ensure that there are procedures available
under their national law for all of the forms of cooperation which are specified
under this Part". Where a party state fails to comply with a request to
cooperate with the Court, "the Court may make a finding to that effect and
refer the matter to the Assembly of State Parties or, where the Security
Council referred the matter to the Court, to the Security Council".
Even in the case of competing requests, the request for surrender by the
Court would take precedence over a similar request for extradition of the
same person by another state.
26
Here, it is important to note that the Court
uses the term 'surrender' instead of extradition,
27
which is normally used when
the transfer of criminals between two states based on a treaty is involved. The
use of the term 'surrender' legitimizes the authority vested in the Court.
'Surrender' denotes authority and an order that needs to be complied with.
'Extradition' means request, which a state may or may not comply with.
Moreover, the dictionary meaning of 'extradite' means handing over of a
criminal to the foreign state, where the crime was committed. Since the ICC
involves trying criminals who may have committed an offence not only in a
Page 9
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
9
foreign land but anywhere in the world, even in their own country, hence the
usage of the term 'surrender'.
In matters of national security, the 3Court does grant some concessions to
state parties for protection of national security information. Article 72 of the
Statute contains adequate safeguards to allow party states to protect sensitive
national security information that might potentially be used as evidence at
trial. Party states can refuse to divulge information that is prejudicial to their
national security interests.
The two cornerstones of a sovereign state are independent foreign policy
and national security. Here, one sees that while the Court shows respect for
national security of the states, it does not accord the same status to its foreign
policy. Irrespective of the foreign policy compulsions of the states involved,
Article 90 grants priority to request for surrender by the Court over similar
requests by other states for extradition of the same individual. The United
States, which had played a significant role during the negotiations phase,
finally decided to remain a non-signatory. But, what is more intriguing is that in
the end the US was clubbed with the so-called 'evil states' (Iraq and Libya)
who had voted against the treaty. India too opposed the treaty.
One of the main reasons cited by almost all those who opposed the treaty
is that, the ICC goes against the concept of national sovereignty. But, each
country has its own idea and definition of sovereignty based on its interests.
Throughout the negotiations, the US' aim was to create greater scope for
wielding power over, and through, the Court, by making the Security Council a
powerful player in the scheme. India, on the other hand, opposed any role
whatsoever for the Security Council. The difference between the Indian and
the US opposition to the ICC, can be located in Hedley Bull's conception of
sovereignty in international relations as antithesis of order and justice-"the
clash between the preoccupation of the rich industrial states with order (or
rather with a form of order that embodies their preferred values) and the
preoccupation of poor and non-industrial world with just change."
28
It is
interesting to note that the Israeli delegation's opposition to the Rome Statute
was based on its demand for extra-territorial sovereignty. Therefore, it
Page 10
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
10
protested against Article 8, Para 2 (b), and sub-para.viii, which included "the
action of transferring population into occupied territory" in the list of most
heinous and grievious war crimes.
29
While there may not be a consensus
among these states on the definition of sovereignty, one thing that all of them
seem to be experiencing is a challenge to their authority.
Why ICC?
The process of holding individuals accountable for human rights abuses
had been on the agenda of international society since the end of the First
World War. Since the First World War, five international investigative
commissions and four ad-hoc international tribunals have been established to
try individuals for crimes against humanity.
30
However, the common
complaint against all these trials has been that they have been carried out at
the behest of the victor.
It goes to the credit of the ICC that it has been brought out with the
consent of a majority of nations to bring about a change in the international
order and not any practice of the victor influencing the course of justice after
the conflict. The Rome Statute was adopted by 121 votes in favour, seven
against and 21 abstentions. The seven countries that cast a negative vote
were the USA, China, Israel, Libya, Iraq, Qatar and Yemen. India abstained.
31
The representatives of 14 international organizations and 236 NGOs
representing some 800 members of the International NGO Coalition for the
ICC also attended the Rome conference.
32
One of the main reasons for the Court to come into existence after the end
of the Cold War is that many crimes committed against humanity have been
ignored by states either due to 'military necessity' or under the national
sovereignty and territorial integrity clause. The ICC does involve a sacrifice of
sovereignty, because it envisages asserting itself when a state refuses or fails
to use its national criminal justice apparatus to deal with the perpetrator of
crime against humanity.
Page 11
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
11
Under the Westphalian system, the sovereign power to make war and
peace is restricted to the legitimate state alone. However, the proliferation of
advanced technology and the ease with which individuals can appropriate
these technologies to cause large-scale destruction challenges the state's
monopoly over the means of waging war. A suicide bomber epitomizes the
sovereign powers inherent in any individual to make war. The ICC's provisions
are not directly related to controlling such atomized individuals who have
broken their agreement of allegiance with civil society and with norms
identified by the international society. However, by providing the irrational
individuals viable media to seek justice, the ICC may help to prevent the
slippage of a greater number of individuals into the Lockean 'state of nature'.
33
The question that comes to mind is why should people hand over their
rights to a supra-national body? The rapid growth of markets devoid of any
soothing political effects has generated a fresh wave of fear in the minds of
people. The growing inequalities and dwindling economic opportunities are a
cause of insecurity in the world. This is one main reason for the growth of
xenophobic, ultra-nationalist and ethnic movements across the world, which
threaten minorities.
The movement towards supra-national legal structures spearheaded by
the global civil society is perhaps a response to the human need to seek
justice which is being denied within many states. Using the Lockean logic, one
can argue that the sovereign individual cannot remain in a perpetual 'state of
nature'. The rational individual, disillusioned with his own government's
response to his needs of comprehensive security, is beginning to offload the
baggage of his natural sovereign rights to a larger terrestrial body like the UN
to ensure his 'peaceful sleep'. Through the ICC, the post-modern individual is
exerting his inalienable right to appeal to a supra-national 'terrestrial body'
which also possesses spatial powers to monitor the activities in various parts
of the world rather than trying to seek justice from a supernatural power.
34
But, how credible and independent the Court will be of the political
compulsions imposed by the stronger powers will have to be seen. The two
Page 12
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
12
ad hoc tribunals, ICTY and ICTR, which are based on selective justice, do not
enjoy very high international credibility ratings.
35
Another reason for the formation of a permanent court is that the ad-hoc
tribunals are time-consuming, relatively expensive and loaded with extensive
logistic problems. The insights provided by Spain's request for the extradition
of Augusto Pinochet from the UK for crimes committed against the Spanish
people in Chile, also proved valuable in the ICC. The Pinochet event set
alarm bells ringing in the international community, because such extradition
could set a precedent. This, according to Antonio Perez, could "become a
vehicle for bootstrapping the exercise of universal jurisdiction into a much
more powerful tool of unilateral law enforcement, where each nation on its
own or perhaps with a slight assist from the rendering state, could become
[an] international policeman."
36
Individual and Sovereignty
The judges of the International Military Tribunal at Nuremberg had
reached a conclusion that "crimes against international law are committed by
men, not abstract entities, and only by punishing individuals who commit such
crimes can the provisions of international law be enforced." This was the first
successful attempt to hold the individual responsible for acts detrimental to
international society. During the inter-War years, attempts were made to
contain national sovereignty and bring the legally invisible individual into the
realm of international law. However, the predominance of state-centricity and
positivist international law prevented any attempts to dilute state authority.
The identification of states as the proper 'subjects' of international law was
formalised with the introduction of bi-polarity at the end of the Second World
War. The individual was ascribed the status of an 'object' in international law.
"As objects, individuals have no rights or liabilities under international law. The
only right or liability they possess are derivatives of states under the principle
governing nationality".
37
It is the conception of the individual as a mere 'object'
in international legal terms that is being contested by the ICC.
Page 13
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
13
The process of conferring certain universal rights to individuals began at
the end of the Second World War.
38
The Helsinki Act of 1975 reiterated the
fact that the relationship between the national governments and their people
was not solely the concern of the state.
39
According to Hideaki Shinoda,
various international human rights conventions "have a great impact upon
traditional anthropomorphisms, because the very notion of individual human
rights goes beyond the simple analogy of natural and state persons." What
this indicates is the decline of the nation as the organic subject of sovereignty
and the state as the sole unit of analysis in international politics.
40
The collapse of the Berlin Wall catapulted the human rights campaign to
new heights through the use of media technology. The overarching presence
of the media and the spread of NGOs in the 1990s led to greater scrutiny of
the serious human rights violations record of states. The increased
surveillance of the state's human development performance has led to the
emergence of new concepts in the field of security. National security based on
maintaining territorial integrity is being replaced by a much broader concept
called 'human security', which "seeks to place the individual-or people
collectively as the referent of security."
41
It is an accepted norm in any society that rights and responsibilities go
hand in hand. The ICC provisions aim to balance the rights conferred on
individuals by international society with responsibilities and accountability to
international law. Does this lead to a kind of 'supra-national citizenship', as in
the case of the European Union, which is "understood not merely as an
agreement among states but also as a 'social contract' among nationals of
those states?"
42
Therefore, what we are witnessing is the international legal
status of the individual undergoing a metamorphosis. The transformation of
the individual from 'object' to 'subject' in international legal terms is resulting in
a shift in power relations both within and between states. This means that the
state's monopoly over its people is fast eroding and its political authority is
being challenged. Since the Sovereign State is still considered to be the best
available institution capable of dealing with human problems in world politics,
we find that ICC's referent is both the state and the individual. However, there
Page 14
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
14
is a problem in combining universality with individualism because the ethos of
individual rights goes against the sense of communal responsibility. According
to Michael Walzer, individualism fosters a "concept of self which is
normatively undesirable".
43
Although the ICC does not involve any official transfer of sovereignty, its
provisions definitely enjoin upon states to share authority over its citizens.
These provisions in the Statute could open the floodgates for intervention in
the internal affairs of states. One senses in the ICC Statute a streak of
Weberian logic according to which, under certain circumstances, "sovereignty
and intervention cease to function as dichotomous terms. If sovereignty and
intervention are everywhere, they are nowhere."
44
To understand Weber's
logic let us consider the US intervention in Afghanistan. After the fall of the
Taliban, the media carried pictures of liberated men and women, giving the
impression that the US intervention was justified to free the Afghan population
from the grip of the Taliban. It could be argued that it was the Taliban, which
had initially pierced the sovereignty of the Afghan people and that the US had
acted in self-defence and intervened only to protect human rights. Till this
point the Weberian logic works. But, the problems start when US troops
based in Afghanistan, during the course of their military operations, begin to
attack the local population of Afghanistan and the government of Afghanistan
is not able to unequivocally condemn US actions.
45
It is at this point that the
need for restoring Afghan sovereignty arises once again and the dichotomy
between sovereignty and intervention begins to resurface.
Towards Constitutional Sovereignty
The charisma of state's authority is under strain.
46
The staggering rise in
intra-state conflicts in the post-Cold War world and the growing tentacles of
transnational terrorism have raised questions about state legitimacy. States
are no longer considered to be the most effective means of enforcing
international norms and order among individuals.
The detailed scrutiny of the human rights records of certain countries by
the international community is leading towards a new international order,
Page 15
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
15
where the absolutes of state sovereignty are being challenged. In the new
international setting stability and order take precedence over equality among
states. The sovereign immunity enjoyed by states is being restricted and
limited by the emergence of international constitutional structures, which exist
beyond the boundaries of states.
The ongoing trends in the discourse on sovereignty suggest that a
perceptible shift is occurring away from the theories of national sovereignty,
which had dominated the post-Second World War world, towards
constitutional notions of sovereignty that intend to limit sovereignty. At the end
of the Second World War, Charles E. Merriam had argued, "sovereignty must
make friends with constitutional values, scientific values, idealistic values,
which are the heart of our new civilization."
47
The right to hold individuals
responsible and accountable and the thrust towards international
humanitarianism are a part of the same cosmopolitan ideology. The advanced
technology available with the international community enables it to look into
the happenings within state territories. The spatial reach of the international
community is leading towards the construction of an international moral
solidarity against infringement of individual rights.
48
The fresh wave of cosmopolitanism is something akin to the medieval
cosmopolitanism, which came via the church. However, one fundamental
difference between the medieval and current cosmopolitanism is that while
the former was based on the authority derived from God, the latter relies on
scientific means of monitoring human activity for its legitimacy.
The growing interconnectivity and interdependence in the world is leading
towards redefining sovereignty in terms of its obligation to international rules.
According to the former UN Secretary-General, Javier Perez de Cuellar,
"Sovereignty and international responsibility are different sides of the same
coin...The nexus between sovereignty and humanitarianism introduces us to
the notions of international rule of law... Sovereignty and international
responsibility leads back to the international rule of law."
49
Page 16
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
16
International responsibilities of states are normally associated with their
external sovereignty. The right to be an equal member in the comity of nations
is an important aspect of external sovereignty. Alan James finds splitting of
sovereignty into external and internal components to be too dangerous for the
unitary character of sovereignty. Sovereignty, according to James is
'constitutional independence', which can neither be shared nor be divided.
50
However, George Sorensen, while acknowledging the impregnability inherent
in 'constitutional independence', pierces the concept of sovereignty by dividing
it into 'constitutive rules' and 'regulative rules'.
51
The core of 'constitutive rules'
is composed of constitutional independence, which remains stable. But
according to Sorensen, the 'regulative rules' remain in a state of flux. The
difference between James' and Sorensen's 'constitutional independence' can
be located in the age-old question: what came first, the egg or the chicken?
While James holds the opinion that international law is the child of
sovereignty, Sorensen believes that sovereignty is a passport for entry into an
already constituted international community. The unitary character of James'
'constitutional independence' leaves no room for any external interference in
the running of the state. However, Sorensen merely sees constitutional
independence as a piece of paper to lure the states into an international
society, where their sovereignty can be regulated through a different set of
norms.
Applying the George Sorensen logic to the recently constituted ICC, one
can safely argue that it does lead to a divided or truncated sovereignty for
states. While the ICC acknowledges the constitutional validity of the states, it
also undermines it by asking states to share their absolute authority, which
they enjoy over their subjects, thus circumscribing their supremacy or
'constitutional independence'. It is claimed that the Court is not a supra-
national body but a membership of international society. It only identifies
certain core constitutional values, which are shared by all national societies.
Therefore, there is no master-slave relationship between sovereign states and
international institutions. However, one sees that states will always be
subordinate to the ICC because, the latter possesses the treaty powers to
force states to comply with its requirements. Transactions between states and
Page 17
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
17
ICC are one-sided. It is only states that are required to give something
(person or documents). ICC is not obliged to give anything in return to states.
The ICC promises not to states but to its subjects, the protection of their
rights.
Conclusion
Working within the realist paradigm, an Indian jurist Radhabinod Pal, in his
landmark dissenting opinion at the Tokyo trials had come up with a verdict 'not
guilty' in favour of the Japanese.
52
Justice Pal had offered the dissenting note
in the year 1948 and had argued that, "so long as the international
organization continues at the stage where trials and punishment for crime
remain available only against the vanquished in a lost war, the introduction of
criminal responsibility cannot produce the deterrent and preventive effect."
Justice Pal's argument could still be used in 2002, because the hierarchies
among nations have not vanished. In fact, the divide between rich and poor
nations in terms of wealth and therefore the power they exert, is continuously
widening. One could support the argument that sovereignty which is
dissipating from weak nations, without getting destroyed, is finally getting
accumulated with big powers. The power and authority enjoyed by the small
nations during the Cold War is diminishing in the age of globalization. The
rules of admission to an international club of nation-states are changing. New
rules, once again dictated by the Western world, are being floated. In the
medieval age, allegiance to Christianity was a prerequisite for entry into the
club. The colonial era saw the demarcation of the world into civilized and non-
civilized colonies. Now, once again, new demarcations based on pre-
modernity, modernity and post-modernity are beginning to appear.
53
The
world is gradually moving towards 'dual sovereignty' or truncated sovereignty,
which, far from being absolute, only gives limited jurisdictional powers to the
territorial state in certain specific spheres that are inconsequential to
international society. In an interconnected and interdependent post-Cold War
world, the choices are becoming limited, as states have become transmitters
of global norms into the national mainstream. Under such circumstances, it
may be better for small and weak nations to pool their sovereignties in
Page 18
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
18
international organizations rather than letting their sovereign energies flowing
towards a few or rather one powerful player in international politics, since the
chances of receiving peace and justice within a larger international
organization are much greater than relying on the sole Superpower to deliver
justice only through war. Therefore, in deciding the future course of action on
strengthening international organizations, rationality rather than realism
should guide the policies of weak and small nations.
If the state is a notional person, then sovereignty is its spine. According to
neo-realists, the strength of spine (economic, military) determines the
domestic and international standing of the country. However, a constructivist
would argue that since no person (state) can keep its spine ramrod straight for
long times, therefore, it is the flexibility of the spine, which enables the state to
perform and maintain a healthy balance between its domestic and
2international obligations. But the moot point is how much a state should bend
to ensure that its back doesn't break. Joining international regimes like the
ICC may not damage sovereignty to an extent to which it would get affected, if
one were forced to enter the global structures created by a global hegemon.
References/End Notes
1.
The text of UN Secretary-General Kofi Annan's speech, to the closing of the ninth session of the
Preparatory Commission for the ICC, April 19, 2002.
2.
Gow, James, A Revolution in International Affairs? Security Dialogue. September 2000, 31 (3) 297.
According to Gow, "popular sovereignty has been ousted as the primary qualification for
statehood by 'equilibriant' sovereignty". Also see Henrik Syse, Ethics, Sovereignty, and Self-
Defence: A Rejoinder. Security Dialogue. December 2000, 31 (4) 437-442.
3.
Kirsch, Philippe and John T. Holmes, Developments in International Criminal Law. Foreword in The
American Journal of International Law. 1999, 93 (2) 1-12.
4.
See Peggy E. Rancilio, From Nuremberg to Rome: Establishing Criminal Court and the Need for
US Participation. University of Detroit Mercy Law Review. 2001, 78 (299) 299-339.
5.
See Christian Tomuschat, International Criminal Prosecution: The Precedent of Nuremberg
Confirmed. Criminal Law Forum. 1994, 5 (2-3) 237-247.
6.
See R Venkata Rao, All Roads may not lead to Rome: A Critique of the New Millennium's
International Criminal Court. International Law Conference on International Law in the New
Millennium: Problems and Challenges Ahead. October 4-7 2001. The Indian Society of
International Law, Souvenir and Conference Papers, 2. p. 647-650
7.
See William A. Sachabas, An Introduction to the International Criminal Court. 2001. Cambridge
University Press. pp. 8-10.
8.
Arsanjani, Mahnoush H., The Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court. American Journal
of International Law. 1999, 93 (2) 22-43
9.
Ibid., p.23
10. Kirsch, Philippe, and John T. Holmes, no.3, p.3
Page 19
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
19
11. Ibid., p.3 and Mahnoush H. Arsanjani, no.8, pp. 22-43
12.
For details on various types of crimes see Michael N. Schmitt and Major Peter J. Richards, Into
Uncharted Waters: The International Criminal Court. Naval War College Review. Winter 2000,
53 (1) 93-134. Also see Christopher Keith Hall, The Jurisdiction of the Permanent International
Criminal Court Over Violations of Humanitarian Law. In Flavia Lattanzi, Ed. The International
Court Comments on The Legal Draft Statute. Editoriale Scientifiica. 1998, pp.19-47 and David
Donat Cattin, Crime Against Humanity. In Ibid., pp. 49-93.
13.
Lattanzi, Flavia, The Complimentary Character of the Jurisdiction of the Court with Respect to
National Jurisdiction. In Flavia Lattanzi, no. 12, p. 6-8. The states' preference for repression of
the conventional crimes under the state jurisdiction influenced the contents of ILC draft code of
crimes against peace and security of mankind. Eight categories of crimes, which were a part of
the 1991 approved draft, have been omitted in the ILC draft approved in 1996. The crimes
excluded are intervention in international affairs, colonial domination, international terrorism,
international illicit drug traffic, mercenary soldiering.
14. Kirsch, Philippe, and John T. Holmes, no.3 p.10.
15. Ibid. p. 277.
16. See M Cherif Bassiouni, Explanatory Note on the ICC Statute. International Review of Penal Law.
71 fn. 21 p.7. It is to be noted that in case of all other trigger mechanism, the term 'situation'
has been used, which is intended to exclude a possible selectivity of instances or individuals to
be referred to the ICC on an exclusive basis.
17. See Jelena Pejic, The United States and the International Criminal Court: One Loophole too Many.
University of Detroit Mercy Law Review. 2001, 78 (267) 283.
18.
A statement by Dilip Lahiri, Additional Secretary, MEA, India, speaking on the adoption of Rome
Statute of the international court, July 17 1998 at www.un.org/icc/speeches
19. Lattanzi, Flavia, no. 13, p. 10.
20. See M Cherif Bassiouni, no. 16, p. 8.
21. Ibid.
22.
In an unprecedented step the US unsigned the Rome Treaty on May 6, 2002, which had earlier
been signed by Bill Clinton in 2000. Never in the history of the UN had any country unsigned a
treaty.
23.
For details see Geoffrey S. Corn and Jan E. Aldykiewicz, New Options for Prosecuting War
Criminals in Internal Armed Conflicts. Parameters. Spring 2002, 30-43.
24.
Benison, Audrey I., International Criminal Tribunals: Is there a Substantive Limitation on Treaty
Power? Stanford Journal of International Law. 2001, 37 (75) 85. The author says that
"genocide is difficult crime to prosecute because of high definitional threshold'.
25.
Part 9, Article 86-102 of the Rome Statute deals with international cooperation and judicial
assistance. See Rome Statute at www,un.org/icc.
26. See Rome Statute Part 9 Article 90 at www.un.org/icc
27.
Article 102 of the Rome Statute differentiates between surrender and extradition. (a) 'Surrender'
means the delivering up of a person by a state to the Court, pursuant to this Statute. (b)
'extradition' means the delivering up of a person by one state to another as provided by treaty,
convention or national legislation.
28. See Hideaki Shinoda, Re-Examining Sovereignty: From Classical Theory to the Global Age. 2000.
Macmillan; London. p. 137.
29. See the statement by judge Eli Nathan, head of the delegation of Israel to Rome conference, July
17, 1998 at www.un.org/icc/speeches
30. The 1919 Treaty of Versailles had provided for the establishment of an international tribunal for the
trial of German Emperor, Kaiser Wilhelm, for a supreme offence against international morality
and sanctity of treaties. See M. Cherif Bassiouni, no. 16, p. 3, and Jules Deschenes, Towards
International Criminal Justice. Criminal Law Forum. 1994, 5 (2-3) 252.
31. See Jelena Pejic, no. 17, pp. 267-297.
Page 20
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
20
32. Ibid. p. 271.
33. Locke's state of nature deals with moral autonomy of the individual and is identified as the perfect
state of freedom in which the individual has the natural power. An individual possesses the
power to judge his actions. For detailed analysis of state of nature and state of war see John T.
Scott, The Sovereignless State and Locke's Language of Obligation. American Political
Science Review. September 2000, 94 (3) 547-560.
34.
Ibid., p.552. According to Locke, if "the body the people, or any single man, is deprived of their
right... and have no appeal on earth, there they have the liberty to appeal to heaven, whenever
they judge the cause of sufficient movement". For 'material context in state of nature
arguments' see Daniel H. Deudney, Regrounding Realism: Anarchy, Security and Changing
Contexts. Security Studies. Autumn 2000, 10 (1) 1-42.
35.
According to the Indian delegation at the Rome conference, the decisions to set up the
International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTFY) and for Rwanda (ICTR) were
dictated by the Security Council and are therefore of 'dubious legality' because the powers of
the Security Council cannot be challenged. See Usha Ramanathan, For an International
Criminal Court. Frontline. August 1-14, 1998, 15 (16).
36.
For details on Pinochet case, see Antonio F. Perez, The Perils of Pinochet: Problems for
Transnational Justice and Supranational Governance Solution, Denv. J. Int'l L. & Pol'y, 28 (2)
193.
37.
Cutler, A. Claire, Critical Reflections on the Westphalian Assumption of International Law and
Organization: A Crisis of legitimacy. Review of International Studies. 2001, 27 141.
38.
In 1950, the UN General Assembly "recognized the right of peoples and nations to self-
determination as a fundamental human right".
39.
Gelber, Harry G., Sovereignty through Interdependence. 1997. Kulwer Law International; London.
p. 76.
40. Shinoda, Hideaki, no. 28, p.148.
41.
Newman, Edward, Human Security and Constructivism. International Studies Perspectives. 2001,
2 251.
42.
Quoted by Robert Jackson, Sovereignty in World Politics: A Glance at the Conceptual and
Historical Landscape. In Robert Jackson Ed. Sovereignty at the Millennium. 1999. Blackwell
Publishers; The Political Studies Association; USA. p. 29.
43.
As quoted in Thomas M. Frank, Are Human Rights Universal. Foreign Affairs. January/February
2001, 196.
44. Quoted in Hideaki Shinoda, no.28, p. 6.
45. See Marc W. Herold, The Massacre at Kakarak. Frontline. August 16, 2002, 66-72.
46.
See John H. Schaar, Legitimacy in the Modern State. 2000.Transaction Publishers; New
Brunswick, USA. Schaar has written some thought provoking essays on legitimacy and
authority of the state in modern times. He is of the opinion that both in terms of providing
security as well as material satisfaction the states, including the most powerful ones are falling
far behind the expectations of their citizens.
47.
British intellectuals like Carr, Leonard Woolf insisted on limiting sovereignty to uphold the rule of
international law. Similarly, in America too people like Edward S. Crown, Charles E. Merriam
stressed the need for amalgamation of sovereignties to enhance its power and reach. For
details see Hideaki Shinoda, no.28, pp. 100-103.
48.
For details on increased satellite surveillance capacity of the UN, see Paul Taylor. The United
Nations in the 1990s: Proactive Cosmopolitanism. In Robert Jackson, no. 42, pp. 116-143.
49. See Hideaki Shinoda, no. 23, p. 160.
50.
Sovereignty as 'Constitutional independence' stands for a unitary condition. That means the
sovereign state is the one supreme authority deciding over internal as well as internal affairs.
See Alan James, The Practice of Sovereign Statehood in Contemporary International Society.
In A. Claire Cutler, no. 37, pp. 35-51.
51.
For details see, George Sorensen, Sovereignty: Change and Continuity in a Fundamental
Institution, Ibid. pp. 168-182. 'Regulative rules' for example are non-interference and
reciprocity.
52. For detailed discussion on Radhabinod Pal's verdict on Tokyo trials see Latha Varadarajan, From
Tokyo to Hague: A Reassessment of Radhabinod Pal's Dissenting Opinion at the Tokyo Trials
on its Golden Jubilee.
Page 21
Strategic Analysis, Vol. 27, No. 1, Jan-Mar 2003
© Institute for Defence Studies and Analyses
21
53. Jackson, Robert, no. 42, p. 15.
Lt. Cdr. Atul Bharadwaj is Research Fellow at IDSA. An alumnus of the
National Defence Academy, Pune, he was commissioned in the executive
branch of the Indian Navy in 1987. He has served on board various ships and
establishments. He has published articles on defence matters and is
presently working on 'globalisation and national security'.

No comments: